Authentic moral commitment — Kant's phenomenology of respect Paul Crowther This paper addresses Kant's complex arguments about the main kind of moral feeling. In Part I, I shall outline the structure of Kant's arguments concerning respect as they are presented in Book One, Chapter III of the second Critique. In Part II, I shall go on to criticise the claims to a priori status which Kant makes for respect; and in Part III will disentangle his major insights concerning it from this surrounding narrative of transcendental idealist epistemology. Finally, In Part IV, I shall develop these insights and thence restate the theory of respect in a way that is both consistent with Kant's ethical theory as a whole, and of more general significance. Part I Kant's general pattern of argument in Chapter III (Book One) of the second Critique is a relatively straightforward one. After his introductory comments, he proceeds to outline the negative and positive aspects of respect in turn, and then repeats this sequence some four or five times - with occasional detours wherein respect's broader social and theological significance is considered. What makes Kant's argument so difficult to grasp, however, is the fact that in each of his repetitions he tends to introduce new emphases and new points of detail - in a way which sometimes conflicts with his position as previously outlined. Rather than trace this extended development in detail, I will attempt to condense Kant's exposition and focus on the logical progression of his arguments. First, Kant holds that whilst a finite rational being cannot hope to explain why the moral law is able to determine the will, it is nevertheless possible to describe its effects. In order to show how the incentive for morality is provided, then, Kant proposes to carefully describe the effect of the moral law's determination of the will upon the faculty of desire. In essence, this effect is negative. As Kant puts it »... all inclination and every sensuous impulse is based on feeling, and the negative effect on feeling (through the check on the inclinations) is itself feeling. Consequently, we can see a priori that the moral law as a ground of This is a revised version of a paper presented to Mr Alan Montefiore's senior Kant Seminar at Balliot College, Oxford\ on May 25th 1988. I am indebted to the participants for their comments, and, in particular, to Mr Montefiore, Professor Onora O'Neill, and Mr Andrew Harrison. 44 Paul Crowther determination of the will, by thwarting all our inclinations, must produce a feeling which can be called pain. On these terms, then, to make a moral decision involves the restraining of contrary impulses. Since this restraint involves a modification of feeling it »must« itself be experienced as a feeling - of a negative sort. Kant then offers us a complex analysis of this affective state. On the one hand it temporarily »checks« inclinations to »self-love« or »selfishness«. The reason why this checking is not total is that these sorts of inclinations are natural and active in us, and can be enjoyed with impunity to the degree that they do not lead us to neglect our moral duties. On the other hand, the will's determination by the moral law altogether strikes down or »humiliates« inclinations towards »self- -conceit«. Now Kant gives - without remarking upon it - two rather different accounts of what constitutes »self-conceit«. His first full account occurs well on into Chapter III as follows. We are told that the propensity to »... make the subjective determining ground's of one's choice into an objective determination of the will in general can be called self-love; when it makes itself legislative and an unconditional practical principle, it can be called self- -conceit.«? Hence, when we act in a spontaneous way from motives founded on purely personal interest we exemplify self-love; but if we make this sort of motivation into a supreme principle of conduct i.e. adopt some kind of egoist sense of self or world-view, then we exemplify self-conceit. It is this self-conceit which the moral law totally »humiliates«. (The reason for this humiliation is not fully spelt out by Kant, and I shall return to it at the end of this section.) Now the second interpretation of self-conceit is most fully stated even further on in Chapter III. It occurs in the context of one of Kant's detours into the broader social signification of respect. He remarks as follows. .»... to a humble plain man in whom I perceive righteousness, my mind bows whether f choose or not ... Why? His example holds before me a law which strikes down my self-conceit when I compare my own conduct with it; that it is a law which can be obeyed, and consequently is one that can actually be put into practice, is proved before my eyes by the act. <•? Kant's point, then, is that exemplars of moral rectitude and (one presumes) one's own awareness of the exacting standards set by the moral law, humiliate self-conceit in the sense of shattering our moral complacency. They illuminate just how far in practice we fall short of such standards. Given, therefore, this now complete outline of the negative dimension of respect - in terms of the checking of selfish inclination, the humiliation of 1. Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, (Translated by A. W. Beck), University Press of Chicago, Chicago 1949, p. 182. 2 . Ibid, p. 184. 3 . Ibid, p. 181. A u then tic moral commitment 45 egoism and the shattering of moral complacency, we are now in a position to consider the positive aspects of the feeling. These are first introduced by Kant in the following passage. »Since /the moral/ law ... is in itself positive, being the form of an intellectual causality, i.e. the form of freedom, it is at the same time an object of respect, since, in conflict with its subjective antagonists (our inclinations), it weakens self-conceit... /hence/ it is an object of the greatest respect and thus of a positive feeling which is not of empirical origin. «* This awkwardly constructed passage is entirely typical of Kant's general style of expounding the positive dimension of respect. It suggests that there are two somewhat different aspects to this dimension - one based on the moral law's positive status as the exemplar of free rational agency; and other based on its causal efficacy in the humiliation of self conceit. That this apparent twofold aspect is not simply a function of Kant's awkwardness of presentation is demonstrated by the fact that at other points in Chapter III he discusses the two elements completely independently of one another. I shall now consider them in turn, beginning with the more difficult notion of the moral law's causal efficacy. The clearest exposition of this is to be found in the following passage. »Since the idea of the moral Jaw deprives self-love of its influence and self conceit of its delusion, it lessens the obstacle to pure practical reason and produces the idea of the superiority of its objective law to the impulses of sensibility; it increases the weight of the moral law by removing, in the judgement of reason, the counterweight to the moral law which bears on a will affected by the sensibility. <