Andragoška spoznanja, 2017, 23(3), 17-34 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4312/as.23.3.17-34 UDK: 37.015.4 Znanstveni prispevek Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther RADICALISING CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION ABSTRACT Democracy faces two key threats today. The first is evident in the growth of authoritarian, right-wing, populism which is evident in a number of European countries and beyond. The second has been the un- dermining of democratic life by neoliberalism. Liberal democracy has aided the latter by the separation of economics from politics and the focus on the individual at the expense of the public sector and the common good. At the same time, some of the virtues of liberal democracy – the separation of powers, for example – are threatened by authoritarianism. We argue the importance of a critical engagement with current versions of democracy by drawing on a more participatory and active democratic tradition. This has significant implications for how we view citizenship and citizenship education. The dominant ver- sion of citizenship education in Scotland and the UK (possibly in Europe too) embodies a ‘minimalist’ model of citizenship through a curriculum for taking personal responsibility. This is inadequate for the challenge democracy faces. We argue the need to ground citizenship education in more radical soil, to nurture a critically engaged and active citizenry capable of challenging the democratic threats of right- wing populism and neoliberal subjectivity. Keywords: democracy, citizenship education, neoliberalism, populism, radical tradition of adult edu- cation, ‘really useful knowledge’ RADIKALIZACIJA DRŽAVLJANSKE VZGOJE – POVZETEK Demokracija se danes sooča z dvema glavnima grožnjama. Prva je očitna, to je vzpon avtoritarnega de- snega populizma, ki ga vidimo v številnih evropskih in drugih državah. Druga grožnja je spodkopavanje demokratičnega življenja prek neoliberalizma. Temu pomaga liberalna demokracija z ločevanjem eko- nomije od politike in z osredotočanjem na posameznika na račun javnega sektorja in javnega dobrega. Hkrati so pod udarom avtoritarnosti nekatere kreposti liberalne demokracije – na primer ločitev oblasti na tri veje. V članku zagovarjamo pomen kritičnega angažmaja v sodobnih različicah demokracije, tako da pri tem črpamo iz bolj participativne in aktivne demokratične tradicije. Takšno delovanje ima pomembne posledice za to, kako vidimo državljanstvo in državljansko vzgojo. Dominantna različica državljanske vzgoje na Škotskem in v Veliki Britaniji (morda tudi v Evropi nasploh) pooseblja »mini- malistični« model državljanstva, kjer učni načrt poudarja osebno odgovornost. Ta koncept ne zadostuje za izzive, s katerimi se danes sooča demokracija. Trdimo, da moramo državljansko vzgojo presaditi v Stuart Moir, PhD, University of Edinburgh, stuart.moir@ed.ac.uk Jim Crowther, PhD, University of Edinburgh, jim.crowther@ed.ac.uk AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 17 4.10.2017 15:12:33 18 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 radikalnejši prostor, ki bo odprl pot za kritično angažiranje in aktivne državljane, kakršni se bodo znali spopasti z desnimi grožnjami demokraciji in neoliberalno subjektiviteto. Ključne besede: demokracija, državljanska vzgoja, neoliberalizem, populizem, radikalna tradicija izo- braževanja odraslih, »res koristno znanje« INTRODUCTION Across Europe citizenship education, particularly in the context of schooling, has grown in prominence for over two decades or more. At the same time, in recent years we have seen a surge in right-wing populism supported by inward-facing nationalist trends and a discourse of prejudice and hatred against migrants. The Brexit result in the UK is one expression of this and, of course, Trump’s victory in the US elections is another. In this article, we question how citizenship education is framed by arguing it typically lacks a critical account of democracy or, when the links between citizenship and democracy are articulated, a liberal democratic model is assumed unproblematically. In our view, this is inadequate and is part of the problem that has to be addressed in renovating citizenship education for the future. Citizenship education without a critical view of democracy and society is more about social control rather than social change whereas the real challenge for citizenship education is to be relevant to the inculcation of an open, participatory democratic culture that contributes to individual and collective agency, whilst making connections between ‘personal troubles’ and ‘pubic issues’ (see Mills, 1959). In the UK, this type of social purpose was noticeable in the best of the liberal and radical traditions of adult education (see Fieldhouse, 1998). However, there is not much of this type of adult or citizenship education around particularly as a ‘human capital’ agenda has dominated lifelong learning (see Biesta, 2006). We argue the need to reassert the relevance, values and purpose of the kind of education which saw itself as enabling citizens to be critically engaged actors in changing society. If we do not take heed of this, the regressive nationalism evident across parts of Europe, the US, India and Turkey, which poses a threat to liberal democracy, may well end up ex- tinguishing the social and political freedoms we associate with it and, as a consequence, other traditions of democracy too. We need to overcome the limitations of liberal de- mocracy (but not throw out what is useful in it) by resourcing a more radical and partic- ipatory democracy which requires a process of collective engagement in public life. We develop this position by exploring the contested conceptions of citizenship education and by reviewing some evidence of the limitations of the dominant conception of citizenship education in the context of schooling. We also draw on field research being conducted by Moir on learning critical citizenship – in and outside schools - to introduce some selective quotes which reflects our position. We do not assume these quotes are representative of the wider population, more that they serve the purpose of vivifying academic arguments rather than empirically substantiating them. It is the nature of the formative experiences AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 18 4.10.2017 15:12:33 19Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education and prefigurative educational work done with young adults that potentially offers us a source of hope for the future. One further qualification. Whilst our argument has, we believe, a European wide rele- vance we draw mainly on sources which have a UK reference point and specifically a Scottish one. It is not that we are uninterested in events elsewhere but simply that we are more familiar with our own contexts and we anticipate the ability of readers elsewhere to draw from this account relevant aspects. We look forward, of course, to accounts which extend and enrich our own horizons. THINKING ABOUT CITIZENSHIP McLaughlin (1992, p. 236) argues that citizenship can be mapped on a continuum ranging from minimal to maximal conceptions. He makes the valid point that this range of under- standings are linked to ‘…different political beliefs and interpretations of democracy’. This can be illustrated by drawing on what he claims are the four key characteristics of citi- zenship; the nature of the identity conferred on an individual by citizenship, the virtues that are required to be a citizen, the extent of the political involvement individuals are required to show, and lastly the particular social prerequisites necessary for effective citizenship. In the minimal view, the nature of identity mainly relates to an individual’s formal legal status and the civic rights and obligations that are conferred on them, such as being able to vote, hold a passport and having a sense of ‘an unreflective nationality’ (ibid., p. 236). A maximal interpretation is seen in much fuller terms. It includes the need for individuals to recognise the rights and responsibilities they have as a member of civic society, yet it is also seen as being much more than this. Individuals should acquire a critical conscious- ness and contribute to a dynamic, shared, democratic culture. They need a sense of ‘the common good and fraternity’ (ibid., p. 236) and the active role they have in creating this. Furthermore, this notion of the common good is ‘dynamic rather than static’ as it should continually be debated and refined, particularly in recognition of the way that citizen- ship relates to notions of equality of access in that participation can be undermined by inequali ties of social class, race, gender or disability for example. In relation to the virtues required by citizens, the minimal approach focuses on ‘loyalty and responsibility’ (ibid., p. 236) to be law abiding with a focus on doing good works such as volunteering or being a good neighbour. The virtues required in the maximal interpretation require ‘a more extensive focus for their loyalty and responsibility’ (ibid., p. 236), with citizens having a responsibility for engaging in critical questioning about existing social conditions and working towards improved social justice and the empower- ment of all citizens. The political involvement of citizens in the minimal interpretation frames citizens as essen- tially private and passive with an obligation to vote when required. Alternatively, a citizen in maximal interpretations would be involved in much more than just voting. They would be expected to engage actively in a participative democratic culture and by doing so they AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 19 4.10.2017 15:12:33 20 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 also sustain and develop it. The social prerequisites involved in the minimal approach are simply the awarding of the legal status of citizen. In the maximal interpretation equality is the key social prerequisite. Therefore, society should do all it can to counter circumstances such as social disadvantage, which can undermine the ability of citizens to participate fully. McLaughlin’s framework problematises the underlying assumptions informing a specific conception of citizenship, and the wider purposes to which the related citizenship edu- cation (CE) is being harnessed. Particularly, what kind of citizen is CE being deployed to create? McLaughlin (1992, pp. 241–242) introduces two kinds of citizen, the ‘autono- mous’ and the ‘autarchic’. The autonomous citizen and their activity would be characteri- sed by critical reasoning and, where required, a challenging of the status quo associated with the maximal conception. The autarchic citizen, however, is framed as being more individualist and self-reliant and their activity would be more limited in scope and in particular would not extend to ‘calling into question fundamental maters…such as the prevailing social and political structures’ (ibid., p. 241). The autarchic citizen would be associated more with the minimal conception. Thus McLaughlin’s framework presents the purpose of CE as being either minimal, pacifying people to except the status quo or maximal, developing critical awareness to promote change. However, it has been the for- mer that has tended to be deployed – at least in the UK – as the interest in CE has grown. This minimalist emphasis is, however, part of the problem that can lead to authoritarian political reactions as democracy and citizenship education appears to merely shore-up liberal political and wealthy elites rather than result in substantive democratic and egali- tarian outcomes. A number of factors have influenced the growth of citizenship education for young people, as we now turn to consider. THE PROMINENCE OF CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION Osler and Starkey (2006) highlight the renewed interest in CE, both in the UK and inter- nationally. By drawing on a systematic review of the literature between 1995 and 2005, they identify ‘six contextual factors’ which explain this growth in interest. We briefly summarise these six factors below. The first factor relates to the notion that education should contribute to helping people understand and challenge global injustice and inequality. This is influenced by the reco- gnition that there is a growing link between inequality and injustice, and the growth in terrorist movements across the world. A key policy driver here is the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC), which contains within it an aim for ed- ucation focused on developing respect for human rights and freedoms and to equip people to live a responsible life in a free society. The second factor relates to the educational response to globalization and the resultant mi- gration. As nation states and geographic communities become increasingly multicultural, there is a tension between the need for education to promote national unity and the need to include and accommodate increasing cultural diversity. Therefore, to promote social AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 20 4.10.2017 15:12:33 21Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education cohesion, CE should inculcate a set of democratic values and ideals such as human rights, justice, equality and tolerance of diversity that all citizens can support and embrace. The third factor relates to the ‘paradigm of disengagement’: the perceived erosion of the civic and political engagement of young people. This perception views young people as apathetic, ignorant and indifferent to the political process. As Biesta (2011, p. 12) com- ments, young people are seen as lacking the ‘…proper knowledge and skills, the right values and correct dispositions to be the citizens that they should be’. The fourth factor focuses on another perceived youth deficit, this time in relation to their lack of appropriate morals and values. For example, there is widespread public concern about the perceived rise of a range of risky and problematic behaviour such as alco- hol consumption, drug taking and sexual behaviour amongst some young people. All of which are seen as emphasising a need for CE to help young people develop the appro- priate views, values and morals (Qualifications and Curriculum Authority, 1998, p. 15). The fifth contextual factor leads on from the end of the Cold War and the subsequent rise and development of liberal democratic states across the world. Education for citizenship is seen here as a key means of helping to develop and sustain these new democracies. The sixth factor comes from the need to address the rise in anti-democratic and racist movements, particularly in Europe. Anti-racism is therefore seen as an important element of and motivation for CE. Not all of these factors are as relevant or play an equal role in shaping the interest in CE in particular nations where the interplay of history and contemporary issues interact in particular ways. In the Scottish context, it would seem appropriate to suggest that all but the fifth factor, focused on rebuilding democracy after the Cold War, are relevant. Impor- tantly, however, some of these contextual factors are also contradictory in relation to the perceived purpose of CE. For example, one factor emphasises respecting rights and learn- ing knowledge and skills to participate actively in the democratic process. Yet, on the other hand, there is a concern about anti-social behavior which leads to a focus on moral duties and individual responsibilities. For example, Wood (2009, p. 149) states; ‘Citizen- ship education, in this mould becomes nothing more than a programme of addressing a young person’s individual political, social and moral deficits’. We now turn to discuss the policy developments for CE in the United Kingdom (UK) with particular reference to Scotland. Whilst some of the policy language resonates with the kind of maximal view of citizenship previously discussed, the reality on the ground, as we shall see is more towards a minimalist version of citizenship. THE SCOTTISH (AND UK) POLICY CONTEXT Munn and Arnott (2009) argue that the work of British political theorist Bernard Crick has had a significant role in shaping the theory, practice and goals of CE across the constituent parts of the UK. They identify these three key goals as; ‘developing political AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 21 4.10.2017 15:12:33 22 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 literacy, community involvement and social and moral responsibility in young people’ (Munn and Arnott, 2009, p. 444). These key goals are reflected in the current Scottish context and CE and the creation of ‘responsible citizens’ is one of the four key purposes of the curriculum. The others being ‘successful learners, confident individuals, and ef- fective contributors’ (see Education Scotland, no date). In Scotland, CE is embedded as a cross curricular theme within the context of the national ‘Curriculum for Excellence’, rather than for example in England where Citizenship Education is a discrete subject area. Four of the contextual factors previously outlined by Osler and Starkey (2006) have in- fluenced developments in CE in Scotland specifically, the challenge of inequality, the perceptions of youth deficits in political engagement and morals, and the focus on rights and justice education. The key policy development in Scotland began in 1999, directly after the re-enactment of a Scottish Parliament with devolved responsibilities for creating legislation in specific areas (including education). The then Scottish Executive (after 2007 renamed the Scot- tish Government) established a working group to report on how Scotland could develop education for citizenship. This working group produced a report titled ‘Education for Citizenship: A Paper for Discussion and Consultation’ (LTS, 2000). A range of further influential papers and reports were produced which focused on the development and im- plementation of the ideas in the original LTS paper and included the embedding of CE in the curriculum for excellence as a core purpose of education in Scotland (see LTS, 2002; Scottish Executive, 2004). For Biesta (2013, p. 101) the LTS 2002 paper was the most significant in shaping the way education for citizenship developed in Scotland, as it not only specified in detail how citi- zenship should be conceived and how education can contribute to this, but also as it became the framework for further developments in the field. Given the significance of this paper, it is important to highlight some of the key ideas which emerge from it. For example, the overall stated goal of the Scottish Government is to develop young people’s capacity for ‘thoughtful and responsible participation in political, economic, social and cultural life’ (LTS, 2002, p. 5). To support this capacity, schools are directed to promote learning opportunities fo- cused on four aspects; knowledge and understanding, skills and competencies, values and dispositions and creativity and enterprise (See Biesta, 2013 or Munn and Arnott, 2009). An important conceptual principle was also established, which positions young people as ‘cit- izens of today rather than citizens in waiting’ (LTS, 2002, p. 8) with the rights and respon- sibilities that go along with this status. Furthermore, it was argued that young people learn most about citizenship when they are actively involved in the process (LTS, 2002, p. 3) and so schools should function in ways that promote democracy and democratic relationships, including enabling young people to apply their rights and responsibilities, such as participat- ing in all the decision making processes that effect their lives in and outside school. The paper conceived of citizenship and CE as being about acquiring capacity through developing skills and knowledge, but importantly it also argues that young people should AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 22 4.10.2017 15:12:33 23Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education be motivated to use this capacity to make decisions ‘…and where appropriate take ac- tion’, infused with a sense of social and environmental responsibility (LTS, 2002, p. 11). Developing young people’s capability for citizenship also included the need for political literacy and the development of political views and values. Yet the paper also recognised that conflicts in values and power relationships exist and so young people would need to develop a critical awareness of these ideas and values. As Munn & Arnott (2009, p. 447) argue, the report saw developing ‘critical autonomy’ in young people as a key element in helping them understand and actively apply their citizenship. This brief overview of some of the core ideas presented in the paper would seem to reflect a ‘maximal’ conception of CE with ideas such as developing critical awareness, active involvement and taking action, all being prominent. However, a minimal conception is a more accurate description of the Scottish approach in practice. CRITICISM OF THE SCOTTISH APPROACH Biesta (2013) makes some important criticisms of the way CE is conceived of and prac- ticed. We draw on two here. He claims there is a strong individualist tendency in the Scottish approach, which undermines collective responsibility. The emphasis is on devel- oping the appropriate capacities and values to participate individually in society, but not to challenge the existing norms. Linked to this criticism, Biesta also argues that despite the rhetoric of taking action and developing critical awareness, this emphasis on indivi- dual responsibility limits the potential for developing effective political action for change. Therefore, he argues that CE, as it is conceived and subsequently practiced, is at risk of being individualised and apolitical, by focusing on young people’s individual responsi- bilities and underplaying the need to help them learn about and promote their active political engagement in the issues that affect their lives. Of course, this critique is not something unique to Scotland. For example, in the English context, Cunningham and Lavalette (2004, p. 258) make a similar criticism about this in- dividualistic and apolitical tendency as they claim young people are ‘...seen as problems to be managed, moulded and reformed rather than as active citizens capable of thinking and making decisions about issues that concern them’. The minimalist version of citizen- ship dovetails with the premises of liberal democracy which, as we have seen, has been one source of authoritarian populist reaction. There is also an echo of these criticisms emerging in the views and experiences of a group of young political activists taking part in Moir’s ongoing doctoral research1. This research 1 This research takes a qualitative approach and involves interviews with between 14 and 18 young activ- ists. The research question is; How do young political activists learn for democracy & critical citizenship? In particular the study is focused on identifying the significant factors the young people in the sample claim led to their political activity and to what extent did any educational experiences influence their becoming active? Moir is currently conducting a detailed analysis of the interview data working towards writing up his thesis in early 2018. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 23 4.10.2017 15:12:33 24 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 is exploring how these young activists account for their activism and what role their ed- ucational experience played in this. The activists taking part in the study are members of three organisations; The Young Communist League, Scottish Labour Young Socialists and Young activist in the Trade Union Movement. Speaking on the aims of Citizenship education in Scotland one respondent comments: “I think they’re great aims and I can get behind them, but I suppose in my view, if this was in place while I was at school, you know, just from what I know from friends…the aspirations (of CE) didn’t match the reality for so many students. And I think, for example it says here about citizens of today, not citizens in wait- ing, but people aren’t taught how to register to vote even. For example in my view something schools fail to do, I think you should be able to register to vote at your school, especially now sixteen and seventeen year olds are eligible to vote. I think there should be support from, citizenship education or even mod- ern studies2 teachers or whatever to help pupils, you know, register to vote. And again, coming back to this point not citizens in waiting, we’re not, schools don’t tell pupils how the political system actually works, how you can get involved. Like, it doesn’t talk about trade unions, like how you connect, it doesn’t even talk about civil society in the sense of how you can get involved in that sense...” He went on to express his concern at his experience of CE commenting; “…so I do worry in a sense, like, reflecting back on what my friends have told me that we essentially have a generation of young people in Scotland who aren’t being, you know, geared towards citizenship or activism, and I think that’s to the detriment of our political process in Scotland.” Another respondent reflecting on the difference between the policy rhetoric and the aims of CE and his lived experience said; “…I think the school, the discipline of school, the hierarchy within school, this is all through primary school, all through high school, does the opposite I think it reinforces just like being subdued, reinforces that discipline. And this isn‘t anything conscious by the teachers in any sense, it’s just when you‘re brought up and you‘re not taught to think critically. Another respondent also emphasized the lack of criticality and an inability to challenge ideas in school. She comments; 2 Modern studies is a subject unique to the Scottish secondary school curriculum. The focus of Modern Studies is to develop learners’ knowledge and understanding of contemporary political and social issues in local, Scottish, United Kingdom and international contexts. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 24 4.10.2017 15:12:33 25Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education “…our teacher, she was a really good teacher but I do remember her having very distinct…distinct definitions of what capitalism was and what communism was. And I remember her describing them as two very different things and how capitalism, you know, was described as something that allowed people to start their own businesses and communism was kind of described as this awful ide- ology that kind of imprisoned people but at, at the time…there was kind of no awareness that we could challenge that view. There was a kind of…this is just it, like we’ll just accept this as it is. And there was no appetite for anybody else to challenge the view that was kind of being taught to us, I suppose. And as some- one that’s now been involved in left wing politics for a while and read more about it… there was no real opportunity to challenge… prevalent ideas or key ideas”. Another respondent reflected on the content of the curriculum and his experience of it commenting; “…I guess, there is a set curriculum, there is only so much you can teach, it would have been nice to have learned a bit more about trade unionism and the labour movement. And I can understand why it is limited as there is so much to teach a class…I guess…the schools are fearful of radicalizing students. I guess from the top down they don‘t want to cultivate a sense of workers solidarity and get people interested in politics...” What lies behind these critiques and the experiences of these young activists is the notion that citizenship and CE are ‘essentially contested’ concepts which ‘…inevitably involves endless disputes about their proper uses on the part of their users’ (Gallie, 1956, p. 169). Citizenship and CE are not neutral. The particular approach adopted at any one time represents a choice from a spectrum of different, and often diametrically opposed, inter- pretations of citizenship and, more importantly, the nature of democracy. CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION IN LIBERAL DEMOCRACY Carr and Hartnett (2002, p. 11) argue that there is a tension ‘…between the ‘liberal’ commitment to individual freedom and the ‘democratic’ commitment to a more equitable distribution of power’. The tension, of course, is between how we value liberty or equality and the balance between the two. Carr and Hartnett compare and contrast what they term as the ‘contemporary’ conception of democracy and the ‘classical’ conception based on Athenian participatory and direct democracies. Carr and Hartnett’s view of contemporary conceptions of democracy see citizenship in a minimal way. For example, there is a representative democratic culture and merely formal notions of equality. A core principle is the development and mainte- nance of a social system that allows individuals to pursue their own private self-interest with a minimum of state interference. This positions citizens as little more than politically AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 25 4.10.2017 15:12:33 26 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 passive voters. Alternatively, for Carr and Hartnett, classical conceptions of democracy frame citizens in a maximal way and encourage their active participation in the political and decision-making process. People are seen as active political beings in a participative democratic culture who share in the deliberations that shape and develop their world. These differing conceptions of democracy, and the citizens required to enact them, have a significant impact on the particular function of CE. According to McLaughlin (2006, see also Carr and Hartnett, 2002), pluralist liberal democracies like the UK are characterised by a diversity of beliefs and values, but especially a diversity in what should constitute the appropriate public virtues, identities, principles and loyalties that shape and sustain the good and just society. Consequently, there is a tension in the operation of a pluralist so- ciety between the ability of individual citizens to pursue their private lives and the extent to which this is constrained by the desire to maintain or enforce particular social norms. As there are these countervailing forces at work in a pluralist democracy there is always a difficult balance to be struck between ‘cohesiveness and diversity’, between our public and private lives and the values which inform them (McLauchlin, 1992, p. 240). McLauchlin suggests that CE in pluralist societies therefore have two key, but contra- dictory roles, to enable students to develop an understanding of and commitment to the various shared public virtues and dominant ideas that characterise society, but also to encourage a critical examination of these public virtues and norms and, when required, change them. Education which focuses on the latter is therefore critical today. The problematic nature of CE therefore follows on from this tension, as it depends where on the minimal/maximal continuum those who are promoting CE choose to draw their particular conception of citizenship from and the purpose this education is thought to serve. Any position taken will be normative, informed by the particular view a person holds on political economy and their view of democracy and citizenship. However, a key test should be to what extent any approach helps to promote and sustain a vibrant demo- cratic culture and challenge inequality and injustice, which is claimed to lie behind the recent interest in CE. A TYPOLOGY OF CITIZENS: STRENGTHS AND LIMITATIONS FOR CITIZENSHIP & DEMOCRACY Westheimer and Kahne (2004) draw on their own empirical research in the United States to develop a typology of citizens and CE (see also Veugelers, 2007 and Johnson and Morris, 2010), which is in many ways consistent with McLaughlin’s maximal and mini- mal conceptions. Westheimer and Kahne suggest three types of citizen: the Personally Responsible Citizen, the Participatory Citizen and the Justice Oriented Citizen. These conceptions reflect different ontological and epistemological assumptions about what a good citizen is and what learning supports them. All three conceptions promote the development of individual knowledge and skills such as how democracy and govern- ment institutions work. However, the Personally Responsible conception differs sharply AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 26 4.10.2017 15:12:33 27Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education from the other versions. Personally Responsible citizenship is focused solely on building individual skills and capacities and promoting traits such as developing good charac- ter, behaving responsibly, obeying the law, volunteering and charity giving; a minimal interpretation in McLaughlin’s terms. Participatory citizenship emphasises community leadership and action, whereas Justice Orientated citizenship as well as involving these things, would also emphasise the development of critical awareness and structural analy- sis of social problems. These would be more closely aligned to a maximalist conception. In relation to the key test of promoting and sustaining a democratic culture, Westheimer and Kahne state that an exclusive emphasis on Personally Responsible citizenship is ‘… inadequate for advancing democracy’ (Westheimer and Kahne, 2004, p. 248). They argue that whilst some of the traits associated with the Personally Responsible citizen, such as ‘fostering honesty, good neighbourliness and so on’ (ibid., p. 244) are in themselves good things for people living together in communities to have, they are not inherently democratic. Emphasising the problem, they go on to argue that ‘…government leaders in a totalitarian regime would be as delighted as leaders in a democracy if their young citi- zens learned the lessons put forward by many of the proponents of personally responsible citizenship’ (ibid., p. 244). Westheimer and Kahne argue that the Personally Responsible conception is the dominant conception in the United States. Our experience of educational practice would suggest that this is the case in Scotland as well. Biesta (2013) also argues that although drawing on elements of all three of Westheimer and Kahne conceptions ‘the Scottish approach is predominantly that of the personally responsible citizen’ (Biesta, 2013, p. 113). The policy documents relating to Scotland could be seen to promote the idea that CE should be about creating and sustaining a ‘healthy and vibrant culture of democratic participa- tion’ (LTS, 2002, p. 11), were by ‘taking action’ (ibid., p. 11) ‘issues of social injustice’ and ‘inequities’ will be addresses (ibid., p. 6). However, in our view and from the findings of Westheimer and Kahne and Biesta, it would seem that serious doubt is cast over the ability of CE, as it is currently conceived in Scotland, to achieve these ends. THE DOMINANCE OF THE PERSONALLY RESPONSIBLE (NEOLIBERAL) CITIZEN The dominance of a personally responsible interpretation of citizenship presents a funda- mental challenge to those interested in CE and its potential for developing a participative democracy and a more socially just world. However, to understand the dominance of this interpretation we need to understand the wider context from which this dominance aris- es. According to Hollis ‘Education is a process of shaping society a generation hence’ (quoted in Carr and Hartnett, 2002, p. 17). The particular shape this takes at any one time is related, dialectically, to the dominant political and economic ideas of the time. The choices we make about education today can lock us into a particular set of social and economic relations for the future. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 27 4.10.2017 15:12:33 28 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 The dominant political economy of today is globalised neo-liberalism, and education policy and practice are being distinctively shaped by its particular nostrums, values and limitations (Garret, 2009; Olsen and Peters, 2005; Crowther, 2004). According to Harvey (2005, p. 2) neoliberalism is; … a theory of political economic practices that proposes that human well-being can best be advanced by liberating individual entrepreneurial freedoms and skills within an institutional framework characterized by strong private pro- perty rights, free markets and free trade. The role of the state is to create and preserve an institutional framework appropriate to such practices. For Harvey (2005, p. 5) neoliberalism, by serving the interest of a small but powerful elite, exacerbates inequalities already inherent in capitalist society in which the oppor- tunities for the majority of people to fully develop and flourish are limited or negated. However, to help understand some of the factors sustaining the dominance of neoliberal- ism, it is important to look more closely at the particular relationship between the role of education and the economy that neo-liberal ideas foster. Ball (2012, p. 2) suggests that neo-liberalism has changed how we think about the na- ture and purpose of education today, including CE. One of the significant effects of this change on education is a tendency towards economic reductionism. For example, Aspin and Chapman (2000) argue that education has a ‘triadic nature’ which includes an eco- nomic purpose for employability and prosperity and a personal element, which relates to an individual’s personal development and growth. It also includes a democratic element, which should foster social inclusiveness, democratic understanding and activity which will help develop and sustain a ‘more democratic polity and set of social institutions’ (ibid., p. 17). Yet crucially, the key for Aspin and Chapman is that these elements are interrelated and indivisible, with a ‘complex interplay between all three’ (ibid, p. 16). However, Biesta (2006) and Crowther (2004) argue that there has been a significant rea- lignment in both the priorities and understandings of this triad over the last three decades. As a result of the dominance of neoliberalism, the economic dimension is now pre-em- inent in education policy, marginalising the other two dimensions of education. As Crowther claims (2014, p. 26), ‘In these neoliberal times the justification for almost everything to do with public policy is measured in terms of its economic value’. The pur- pose of education therefore has shifted from being focused on ‘learning to be’, aimed at developing full, rounded humans and a socially just society, to ‘learning to be productive and employable’, focused on the individual development of human capital, employability and the subservience of education to needs of the economy (Coffield, 1999; Crowther, 2004; Biesta, 2006) This economic reductionism has important consequences for the purpose of education, and by implication, for CE in particular. Part of neo-liberalism’s project is an attempt to remoralise society by nurturing a new sense of ‘flexible’ individualism which shifts the AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 28 4.10.2017 15:12:33 29Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education responsibility for prosperity and welfare from the state to the individual, so people will ‘self capitalise’ over their lifetime (Lingard, 2009, quoted in Ball, 2012, p. 3). For Sennett (1999) this has fundamental implications for human beings leading to the very ‘corrosion of their character’. Education is a key contributor to this remoralisation. However, as Crowther (2004, p. 127) argues, there is a ‘hidden agenda’ in education framed in this way, which involves the ‘…creation of malleable, disconnected, transient, disciplined workers and citizens’. The result of this over emphasis on the economic dimension and on ‘learning to be employable’, reinforces the status quo as education becomes ‘…adaptive rather than transformative…’ (Walker, 2012, p. 386). Rather than creating ‘active subjects in politics’ (Shaw and Martin, 2000, p. 402), who can think critically about the world and their place in it so they can act to change it, the individuals who are disciplined and shaped by this neoliberal discourse in education are positioned as ‘objects of policy’, that is passive economic actors, and so they would resemble in McLaughlin’s term, autarchic citizens. This is also the outcome of the dominance of a Personally Responsible or mini- mal conception of citizenship, which emphasises the individual over the collective and tends towards the creation of individualised, apolitical and uncritical citizens. ‘MERELY’ USEFUL KNOWLEDGE OR “REALLY USEFUL (CITIZENSHIP) KNOWLEDGE” Carr and Harnett (2002, p. 44) argue that the purpose of CE is directly linked to particular concepts of citizenship, democracy and economic relations. For them a contemporary conception of democracy reflects the ‘political requirements of the market economy’. The purpose of CE therefore is to produce the ‘political ignorance and apathy of the masses’. Pedagogically, relationships would be authoritarian or transmissive and focused on developing attitudes and knowledge which fit people submissively into the status quo and prepares them for their role as workers and consumers in a market economy. On the other hand, a classical conception would seek to develop knowledge and attitudes in peo- ple that would facilitate political participation and critical awareness, allowing them to ‘reappraise existing social norms and reflect critically on the dominant social, political and economic institutions of contemporary society’ (ibid, p. 44). The pedagogical rela- tionships here would be democratic and participatory, focusing on democratic delibera- tion and the problematising of lived experience, which could lead to transformation and emancipation, not adaptation to the status quo. The above perspective on the purpose of education reflects an important 19th century debate in adult education about the development of Mechanics Institutes in the United Kingdom (See Fieldhouse, 1998). These Institutes were a notable innovation in education for working adults. In the context of poor economic growth, education was seen as both the problem and solution. The economy was not growing effectively due to the lack of technically skilled workers. In order to overcome this shortfall in skilled labour industria- lists and philanthropists were instrumental in creating many – but not all - ‘Mechanics in- stitutes’. However, whilst the education on offer may have benefited people individually, AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 29 4.10.2017 15:12:33 30 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 these institutes were not designed to develop the critical consciousness of workers. As Engels once asserted; Mechanics’ Institutes…offer classes in the brand of political economy which takes free competition as its God. The teachers of this subject preach the doc- trine that it does not lie within the power of the workers to change the existing economic order…they must resign themselves to starving without making a fuss. The students are taught subservience to the existing political and social order. (Engels, quoted in Fieldhouse 1998, p. 27) As the quotation above highlights, on one side of this historical debate were those who saw education as being primarily about providing workers with the appropriate skills and attitudes to serve the needs of the economy to increase prosperity. On the other were radicals who saw this education as domesticating people into an exploitative socio-eco- nomic situation. For radicals, the education of the mechanics institutes provided ‘merely’ useful knowledge which was instrumental, individualised and adaptive. What the radicals wanted was ‘really’ useful knowledge, which would help people understand their current situation and raise awareness of how they could change it for the better (Johnson, 1988). This debate about the core educational function of these institutions has deep resonance with today. The inter-relationship between conceptions of democracy, the economy and education is crucial in understanding the core purpose of the education that emerges from this re- lationship. They have to be considered as a dynamic inter-related and reciprocal totali- ty, rather than static separate elements. Any change in one will influence and reinforce changes in the others. As a result, there is always a struggle, or ‘long revolution’, as Raymond Williams (Carr and Harnett, 2002) describes it, between those who control and benefit from power and wealth and want to maintain this privileged situation, and those who are exploited by the current status quo and need to change things. This struggle lies at the heart of the contested nature of citizenship and CE. We argue that in the context of a dominant, global neoliberal political economy, it is the ‘contemporary conception’ of democracy that is shaping the nature and purpose of CE and we need to change it too. This creates the conditions for the prominence of a ‘minimal’ or personally responsible approach to CE thereby facilitating a process were young people are being locked uncritically into a world that prepares them ‘…for a new economic reality designed by others.’ rather than preparing people to ‘… shape social reality in more pro- gressive and socially just way.’’ (Hyslop-Margison and Thayer, 2009, p. xvii). CHALLENGING EDUCATION FOR PERSONALLY RESPONSIBLE CITIZENSHIP We need to change what CE means and what kind of democracy it needs to serve; un- less we do this, there is no educational challenge to the growth of right-wing populism. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 30 4.10.2017 15:12:33 31Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education We need to ground CE in more radical soil if it is to be an effective challenge to the limited form of CE that are dominant and, at the same time, present an immanent cri- tique of liberal democracy. The philosophical principles of the kind of radical education we are highlighting are especially drawn from the work and ideas of Karl Marx and those involved with the Frankfurt School such as Max Horkeimer and Theodore Adorno (Johnson and Morris, 2010; Darder, Baltodano and Torres, 2003). The work of Antonio Gramsci and Paulo Freire are also influential. Although radical education is informed by a set of ‘heterogeneous ideas’ (Darder et al., 2003, p. 10), there are some core perspec- tives or principles, which can help to characterise its nature and purpose. For example, it is an overtly political and radical educational philosophy and practice (Kincheloe and McLaren, 2002). It seeks to directly challenge the political economy and social relations of capitalist society, which is characterised by significant inequality and injustice for the majority, limiting their ability to develop to their full potential and become ‘fully human’ (Freire, 1990, p. 21). Radical practice challenges the idea of neutrality in education (Freire, 1985; Apple, 1990). The role of dominant traditions in education in capitalist society ‘…remains one of repro- ducing…inequality…and act[ing] to legitimate its rule and to train people to fit into the social-economic hierarchy’ (Youngman, 1986, p. 21). Therefore, an important idea in so- cial transformation is the concept of hegemony (Quintin, 1971). In developing the concept of hegemony Gramsci drew on this key idea from Marx and Engels (2004, pp. 65–66); Each new class which puts itself in the place of the one ruling before it, is com- pelled, merely in order to carry through its aim, to represent its interest as the common interest of all the members of society…it has to give its ideas the form of universality, and represent them as the only rational, valid ones. Hegemony involves the active consent of people in their own subordination. The role of education in this process is crucial, both in terms of sustaining as well as challenging this hegemony. As Gramsci claims ‘Every relationship of hegemony is necessarily an edu- cational relationship’ (Quintin,1971, p. 350). This opens up the opportunity to develop what Gramsci calls a ‘counter hegemonic’ project; key to this is his distinction between ‘common’ sense and ‘good’ sense. For Gramsci, ‘common’ sense is the uncritical view of the world which most people have and which means they unquestionably accept the key hegemonic claims made about the world and their place in it. The key for Gramsci was to develop in people the critical consciousness of ‘good sense’ (i.e. renovating and making critical what people already know) so they can become aware of their situation and come together to act to change it. It is the development of good sense that will help build an enlightening counter hegemonic project. This process of enlightenment is referred to by Freire as conscientization: ‘the process in which people, not as recipients, but as knowing subjects, achieve a deepening aware- ness both of the sociohistorical reality which shapes their lives and of their capacity to AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 31 4.10.2017 15:12:33 32 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 transform that reality’ (Freire, quoted in Carr and Kemmis, 1986, pp. 157–158). For crit- ics, particularly those who value objectivity and neutrality in pedagogical relationships, such a view of education is overtly motivated by a radical politics which therefore leads to the indoctrination of the people educators work with (Burbules and Berk, 1999; Darder et al., 2003). This criticism is somewhat undermined by the idea that all education is political (Allman and Wallis, 1995). As Freire (1985) argues, claiming to be neutral is in itself political, as this is to side with the powerful and so help maintain their power and privilege and an unequal and unjust world. More importantly, it is essential to re-emphasise the centrality of dialogue as an epis- temological category as well as a pedagogical practice, in Freire’s vision of education. Educators who see themselves as ‘enlightening the masses’ miss the point that knowledge has to be created openly and actively between people who are equals; people bring to the educational relationship different types of experience and expertise, but it is only through dialogue as a pedagogical process that genuine ‘acts of knowing’ occur. Missionary prac- tices to teach people what is best for them are self-defeating and useless; educators with- out humility and reflexive awareness are, ultimately, ‘part of the problem’ rather than ‘part of the solution’. CONCLUSION If education is to play any role in defending and extending democratic life, in the context of contemporary capitalism, it needs to also challenge the limits of liberal democracy and the kind of minimal citizenship ideal that it fosters. The very fact that liberal democracy obscures the role of economic inequalities in political outcomes is a root problem. This account has demonstrated that ideas about CE and its relationship to democracy and the economy are complex and contested. As discussed above, ideas of CE range between minimal conceptions that provide ‘merely useful knowledge’ and which act to pacify peo- ple and reinforce an unjust status quo, and maximal conceptions providing ‘really useful knowledge’ and which aim to raise people’s critical awareness of injustice and work to- wards developing a more equal and just society. We have also suggested that in Scotland, within the context of a dominant neoliberal political economy, there seems to be some disjunction between policy and practice. On the one hand, the aims of policy evoke a maxi- mal conception of CE, and on the other, the interpretation and impact of policy in practice, reflects a more minimal or ‘personally responsible’ approach. If citizens are going to be equipped, however, to combat the ideological messages and false promises of right-wing populism they will need to be far better prepared than this model of citizenship caters for. REFERENCES Allman, P. and Wallis, J. (1995). Gramsci’s Challenge to the Politics of the Left in ‘Our Times’. Interna- tional Journal of Lifelong Education, 14(2), 120–143. Apple, M. (1990). Ideology and Curriculum. London: Routledge. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 32 4.10.2017 15:12:33 33Stuart Moir, Jim Crowther: Radicalising citizenship education Aspin, D. and Chapman, J. (2000). Lifelong Learning: Concepts and Conceptions. International Journal of Lifelong Education, 19(1), 2–19. Ball, S. (2012). Global Education inc: New Policy Networks and the New Policy Imaginary. New York: Routledge. Biesta, G. (2006). What’s the Point of Lifelong Learning if Lifelong learning has no Point? On the Demo cratic Deficit of Policies for Lifelong Learning. European Educational Research Journal, 5(3/4), 169–180. Biesta, G. (2011). Learning Democracy in School and Society: Education, Lifelong learning and the Politics of Citizenship. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers. Biesta, G. (2013). Responsible Citizens: Citizenship Education between Social Inclusion and Democratic Politics. In M. Priestley and G. Biesta, Reinventing the Curriculum: New Trends in Curriculum Pol- icy and Practice (pp. 99–115). London: Bloomsbury. Burbules, N. and Berk, R. (1999). Critical Thinking and Critical pedagogy: Relations, Differences and Limits. In T. Popkewitz and L. Fendler, Critical Theories in Education (pp. 45–65). New York: Routledge. Carr, W. and Hartnett, A. (2002). Education and the Struggle for Democracy: The Politics of Educational Ideas. Buckingham: Open University press. Carr, W. and Kemmis, S. (1986). Becoming Critical: Education, Knowledge and Action Research. Lon- don: The Falmer Press. Cohen, L. and Manion, L. (1994). Research Methods in Education. London: Routledge. Coffield, F. (1999). Breaking the Consensus: Lifelong Learning as Social Control. British Educational Research Journal, 25(4), pp. 479–499. Crowther, J. (2004). In and Against Lifelong Learning: Flexi- bility and the Corrosion of Character. International Journal of Lifelong Learning, 23(2), 125–136. Crowther, J. (2014). A Distinctive Vision: Adult Learning in Scotland for Scotland: Lifelong, Life wide and Learner Centered. Adults Learning, 25, 26–28. Cunningham, S. and Lavalette, M. (2004). ‘Active Citizens’ or ‘Irresponsible Truants’? School Student Strikes Against the War. Critical Social Policy, 24(2), 255–269. Darder, A., Baltodano, M. and Torress, R. D. (2003). Critical Pedagogy: An Introduction. In A. Darder, M. Baltodano and R. D. Torress (eds.), The Critical Pedagogy Reader (pp. 1–20?). London: Rout- ledge Falmer. Education Scotland (no date) Education for Citizenship (2001). Retrieved from http://www.education- scotland.gov.uk/learningandteaching/learningacrossthecurriculum/themesacrosslearning/globalciti- zenship/educationforcitizenship/index.asp. Fieldhouse, R. (1998). A History of Modern British Adult Education. Leicester: National Institute of Adult & Continuing Education. Freire, P. (1985) .The Politics of Education: Culture, Power and Liberation. London: Bergin & Garvey. Freire, P. (1990). Pedagogy of the Oppressed. London: Penguin Books. Gallie, B. (1956). Essentially Contested Concepts, Proceedings of the Aritotelian Society. New Series, 56(1955 –1956), 167–198. Garrett, P. M. (2009). ‘Transforming’ Children’s Services? Social Work, Neoliberalism and the ‘Modern’ World. New York: Open University Press. Harvey, D. (2005). A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Hyslop-Margison, E. J. and Thayler, J. (2009).Teaching Democracy: Citizenship Education as Critical Pedagogy. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers. Johnson, L. and Morris, P. (2010). Towards a Framework for Critical Citizenship Education. The Curricu- lum Journal, 21(1), 77–96. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 33 4.10.2017 15:12:33 34 ANDRAGOŠKA SPOZNANJA 3/2017 Johnson, R. (1988). ‘Really Useful knowledge’ 1790 – 1850: Memories for Education in the 1980’s. In T. Lovett (ed), Radical Approaches to Adult Education: A Reader (pp. 33–4). London: Routledge. Kincheloe, J. and McLaren, P. (2002). Rethinking Critical Theory and Qualitative Research. In Y. Zou and E. T. Trueba (eds.), Ethnography and Schools: Qualitative Approaches to the Study of Education (pp. 87–137). Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield. Learning and Teaching Scotland (2000). Education for Citizenship: A Paper for Discussion and Consul- tation. Dundee: Learning & Teaching Scotland. Learning and Teaching Scotland (2002). Education for Citizenship: A Paper for Discussion and Develop- ment. Dundee: Learning & Teaching Scotland. McLaughlin, T. H. (1992). Citizenship, Diversity and Education: A Philosophical Perspective. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 21(3), 235–250. Marx, K. and Engels, F. (2004). The German Ideology. London: Lawrence and Wishart. Mills, C. W. (1959). The Sociological Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press. Munn, P. and Arnott, M. (2009). Citizenship in Scottish Schools: The Evolution of Education for Citi- zenship From The Late Twentieth Century to the Present. History of Education, 3(3), 437–454. Olsen, M. and Peters, M. (2005). Neoliberalism, Higher Education and the Knowledge Economy: From the Free market to Knowledge Economy. Journal of Education Policy, 20(3), 313–345. Osler, A. and Starkey, H. (2006). Education for Democratic Citizenship: A Review of the Research Policy and Practice 1995 – 2005. Research Papers in Education, 24(4), 433–466. Qualifications and Curriculum Authority (QCA)– Education for citizenship and the teaching of democracy in schools. (1998). London: Qualifications and Curriculum Authority. Quintin, H. and Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1971). Selections From the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gram- sci. London: Lawrence & Wishart; New York: International Publishers. Scottish Executive (2004). A Curriculum for Excellence. Edinburgh: Scottish Executive. Sennett, R. (1999). The Corrosion of character: The Personal Consequences of Work in the New Capi- talism. London: W.M. Norton & Company. Shaw, M. and Martin, I. (2000). Community Work, Citizenship and Democracy: Re- making the Con- nections. Community Development Journal, 35(4), 401–413. Veugelers, W. (2007). Creating Critical-Democratic Citizenship Education: Empowering Humanity and democracy in Dutch Education. Compare: A Journal of comparative and International Education, 37(1), 105–119. Walker, M. (2012). A Capital or Capabilities Education Narrative in a World of Staggering Inequalities. International Journal of Educational Development, 32, 384–393. Westheimer, J. and Kahne, J. (2004). What Kind of Citizen? The Politics of Educating for Democracy. American Educational Research Journal, 41, 237–269. Wilkinson, R. and Pickett, K. (2010). The Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do Better. London: Penguin Books. Wood, J. (2009). Education for Effective Citizenship. In J. Wood and J. Hine (Eds.), Work with Young People (pp. 141–153). London: Sage. Youngman, F. (1986). Adult Education and Socialist Pedagogy. London: Croom Helm. AS_2017_3_FINAL.indd 34 4.10.2017 15:12:33