J?azprove in qradivo. Ljubljono. 1999. si. 35 273 Albert F. Reiterer WHO BELONGS TO "US"? The politics of citizenship - a nodal point of democratic legitimacy: ethnos as demos. Introduction Let me start with a statement I do not wholly agree with, more because of its mood than of its undeniable conceptual validity (Oldfield 1990, 8): "Citizenship is exclusive: it is not a persons humanity that one is responding to, it is the fact that he or she is a fellow citizen, or a stranger. In choosing an identity for ourselves we recognize both who our fellow citizens are, and those who are not members of our community, and thus who are potential enemies". In stating this, the author neglects plainly the emancipative potential of the concept of citizenship for universalizing the criteria for political membership. Drawing boundaries is not the same like exclusivism. This misunderstanding is likely to bear undesirable political consequences: Right wing extremism today has its strongest argument in confronting the new migration. This is the only point where it is in touch with the mood of a considerable part, indeed, with the majority of the population. Governmental policies in most Western European States (including Austria) tend to cede to this joint pressures of right wingers and "ordinary citizens". They seem to believe that by restricting accessability to their territory or restraining conditions for citizenship to people of certain types of origin (cf. the Swiss model with its "three circles" of prefered immigrants) they will refrain extremism - while not being aware to further this way extremism by acknowledging as valid its basic assumption. In fact, the new discussion on citizenship and social membership made clear: One of the core questions of democratic rule, of "representative government" (Mill 1975 [1861]) is: Who are those towards whom this order must be legitimated? Of whom consists and what constitutes the demos? Unfortunately, most of the rationalist theoreticians tended to forget that society is always to some degree community. Demos in social reality presupposes ethnos, because only those are admitted to participation - the constitutive element of demos - who are regarded being of the same "stock", of the same "race", as past times liked to say and in present times is often repeated. This said, however, the problems begin, because the nature of this concept (ethnos) is by no means clear, neither is the relationship between ethnos and demos. This paper investigates the complex interconnection between society and community, of demos and ethnos and tries to draw some political conclusions. 274 Albert F. Reiterer: Who belongs to "US'" Foundations Political systems functionally are working as steering mechanisms of societies. This is, however, a rather narrow concept of politics, especially if applied to modern polities. In our complex world the most important political system - the nation-state - is in its personal and in its territorial boundaries usually coterminous with a society, although organizing only a part of human life-worlds and of their members' interests. As states are built on power and violence, as these political organizations at the same time are supposed to aim to organize social well-being and as this means caring for basic needs of their members, they are bound to be legitimized by their members who are subject to their power ("obligations") and who are eligible for their services ("rights"). This leads to the question for the territorial boundaries (as power can only be exercised against those who are within the reach of the powerholders) and for the personal substratum (those who are entitled to the services). It is this latter aspect of the social and political system we are interested in here. The person who has been accorded standardized obligations to the state and can claim formal rights is labeled a citizen. In this world of valued rights and often suspiciously looked at obligations, of course, the problem arises: Who is a citizen, or, as this is a formal question decided on juridical grounds: Who ought to be a citizen? I am asking neither a moral nor a normative question. I try to put the problem who is factually and not only juridically acknowledged by the population as a "real" citizen - a "real" Slovene, a "real" Austrian - which can socially claim to be counted among "Us". It is the problem of legitimate and full membership in our society which solely is giving the right to be also a member of the state which is on its turn administering politically this social membership. By putting the question this way we are distinguishing the society (the "terminal social system") from the state. Although "state" is not an all-encompassiong system but organizes only part of the life-worlds we are refer-ing to; although it disposes only about some of the society's resources we need for survival, the concept is burdened symbolically in such a degree that membership in this subsystem decides virtually about the quality our social membership assumes. Not every person who resides in a country is entitled to full membership in this country's state. Citizenship rules are strongly determined by specific state interests and defined by the state's political elite. They result from a particular concept of nationhood or, sometimes, from the specific position in the international system. A "republican" concept of nation which is coined by an understanding of the nation as a political project - it was this concept which prevailed for a short time in the French Revolution - would allow for more openess regarding those who are until now strangers or "foreigners", but who would possibly become co-nationals. A narrowly defined shared ethnic origin would it make almost impossible to co-opt co-nationals among those who would be ready to fojzprave in grodivo. Ljubljana. 1999, si. 35 275 enter a nation because of sharing the same basic (political) values. So there may be potential consent in entry on the one side (the would-be immigrants), however, refoulment on the grounds of a supposed difference on the other side (the aimed-at state). New Wine in Old Bottles? Some Reflections of the Founding Fathers We have no better concepts for founding liberal democracy than those which have been lumped together by political theory under the label of contract theory. In aiming to free political theory of the iron fist of theological transcendency and from the political dangers of interference by those who direct their loyalty not to their co-citizens Thomas Hobbes.John Locke, and J.-J. Rousseau conceived of the state as a voluntary association of persons wanting to live together for reasons of security as well as for reasons of enhancing general well-being by co-operation. Their conceptual tools have been determining the political thinking unto the very presence. John Rawls (1979), f. i-, has reassumed the nodal point of their reasoning for trying to build on a secure fundament for starting in considering what should be regarded as "just" - "justice" being the core concept of every philo-sophico-political dicussion among modern humans. The classical dieorist, however, passed over a double strategic dilemma and a paradox: Rational and self-interested actors generally have no incentives to contribute voluntarily to the burdens of the state's maintaining because those who contribute nothing to its effort will get just as much (in security, in communication, ...) as those who make a contribution. This would lead to lacking stability for the political system. Max Weber (1976, 122), f. i., saw the consequences of the preponderance of what he called the "rational behaviour": Purely material and target-oriented motives of the members of a political organisation will entail low stability of this system. Thus, he introduces the term of legitimity to care for the stability of his types of dominance. It is the famous (or ill-famed) issue of the free-rider. If there is only voluntary and rational individual behavior then for the most part government will not exist nor will exist states (and societies) (Olson 1968 and 1982). While this difficulty was not seen by the aforementioned theorists - as realist persons they did not even think in such a sofisticated way -, they were well aware of another crucial problem. I will it express again in the wording of Olson (1982, 24); "Another problem in organizing and maintaining socially heterogenous groups is that they are less likely to agree on the exact nature of whatever collective good is at issue." Starting with the willing to abolish unjust political and social power (with Hobbes it is a trifle more complex), the contractualists realized very well that there is a problem of procedures in decision making about the common goals which ends up in a far more problematical issue than being only a technical difficulty. If, f. i., one opts for the principle of majority the will of the minority will be suppressed, and this is oppression as well as if the majority would be concerned. 276 Albert F. Reiterer: Who belongs to "US'" Volonté générale Rousseau tried to solve this paradox by inventing the concept of the general will. The volonté générale, the general will, as foundation of a democratic system conceived by Jean Jacques Rousseau (1966 [17621), is by no means the same as the will of the majority. It is the shared will of all. So, what does this mean effectively if it should be more than a philosophical slogan without any real significance? Rousseau was well aware of the problematical stance of his idea. First, he is warning that power also if exercised by a majority towards a dissenting minority remains power and is needing for legitimity: 'The law of the majority is itself established by convention and needs at least one time unanimity."1 However, he adds: "For the general will to exist it is not necessary that there is always unanimity; but there is necessity that all votes are counted; formal exclusion (of persons or groups) destroys the general character."2 This is a fundamental statement, and Kant (1795, 21) will insist upon this: "Legal freedom, that is freedom against others, is the right not to obey any laws except those to which I had the possibility to consent."3 Let me quote another political theorist of contemporary times with a slightly different subject, speaking about our argument: "Members of the minority, for whatever reason, do not 'count' in the same way as everyone else" (Walzer 1970, 48). Although politically not very often evocated, this argument is a central one in any democratic discourse. Niklas Luhmann (1983) three decades ago has chosen to put the same question by asking for the legitimity of political decisions. He tried to define legitimity as an overall readiness to accept a priori political decisions without regarding if they be in or against my personal interests - if the procedures to come to such decisions are agreed upon and considered fair. However, he neglects that this readiness is bound to some degree to the content of the decisions, that is: They must not violate what I consider my vital interests. If the latter should be the case my agreement cannot be taken for granted, and if I have a chance I will defend myself by all means available, if necessary also by violence,... Luhmann's approach is not satisfying because he argues excusively in terms of interests. In this regard he joins theoretically Rousseau, the contractual-ists and the enlightenment in general. If there is any sense in speaking of a "general will" we have to cease speaking of individual (material) interests. The special interests of all concerned people * * * 1 "La loi de la pluralité des suffrages est elle-mçrne un établissement de la convention, ci suppose au moins une fois l'unanimité" (p. 50"). 2 "Pour qu'une volonté soit générale il n'est pas toujours nécessaire qu'il soit unanime, mais il est nécessaire que toutes les voix soient comptées; toute exclusion formelle rompt la généralité" (p. 64) 3 "Äußere (rechtliche) Freybeit... ist die Befugnis, keinen äußeren Gescuen zu gehorchen, als zu denen ich meine Beystimmung habe geben können." Razprove in gradivo. Ljubljana. 1999. si. 35_______277 will coincide at best sometimes by chance.4 However, the general will ist seen obviously as a basic and total agreement with several dimensions of social entities, rational as well as emotional ones, to consider each other as equal members of one and the same socio-political system. This is social and political consent, not necessarily with a government and not even with a constitution, but with being a member of this particular political community and with sharing its future destiny. The "volonté générale" is to be seen this way as a rationalist concept and expression of what has been told more emotionally by Ernest Rénan (1992 [1882]) as "the desire to stay with one another" ("le désir d'çtre ensemble"). And this is the wording which Rénan gives as his definition of the concept of the nation. The general will is conceived this way as a consciousness of a common and shared identity. Spinoza who is hardly known as a political theorist although he was it in a very deep rooted sense - for him, real humanity was to reach only within a well-ordered state, and therefore he aimed to draw carefully and in great detail its institutions -, has labeled the same need "the deep unity of Man, which is necessary for each organized polity" (1994 [1677], II, § 21). By this he is approaching a concept of identity. His rigid legalism which must be seen as politically substituting what he calls earlier the unity in Being of the nature unfortunately is hampering him to distinguish a concept of legitimily as the political concept contrasting the purely legal concept of legality. He is striving for founding theoretically the monopoly of the modern state in the political sphere against the arrogance of theology and religion as well as against a postulated "natural law" which is itself a disguised metaphysical concept. Thus he does not succeed to formulate a concept of a civil society as an autonomous system compared to the state: He is following theoretically Hobbes and practically the absolutist creed of: "Un roi, une loi, une foi". This could be considered, too, as the creed of the modern ethnona-tional state which has no place for minorities. Rousseau's insight - also the power of a majority is power and is for need of legitimizing - could hardly be neglected with good faith. Thus, the problem of a communitarian foundation of social and political systems, the question of a common and shared identity, has to be faced as a central problem of democracy. Because of this problem - and only because of it - the people's sovereignty had to be transformed to national sovereignty; the sovereignty which constitutes a demos as the sovereignty exercised by an eihnos. Demos, pragmatically, is constituted by participation. Only if demos and ethnos are melting into one social enti- * * * 4 "tin effet, chaque individu peut comme homme avoir une volonté particulière contraire ou dissembleahle à h volonté générale qu'il a comme citoyen" (Rousseau 54). - Saint-Simon (19