Hobbes and the theory of social contract as the context for Kant's political philosophy Gorazd Korosec If we are to deal with Kant's political theory, we must put it in the context of social contract theories. The theory of social contract has a central place in Kant's political theory and by placing it in this tradition, we shall be able to see where his theory is in accordance with the tradition, and where it differs from it. Social contract theory as a mode of political thought has dominated the Age of Enlightenment, but we can also see a revival of such theories in today's political philosophy. We can trace the origins of social contract theory in ancient and medieval thought to Augustine, who built on Seneca and Cicero, to William of Ockham and Nicholas Cusanus, and find a number of basic elements for such a theory in Francisco Suarez, a Spanish writer who saw common political consent as necessary for people to be gathered together in one political body. Talking about its origins, we can also mention the tradition of natural law theory, developed by Grotius, Althusius, Lipsius and Selden, which was subsequently included in a large part in theories of social contract by many of its greatest authors. The idea of individual moral autonomy, grown within the movements of Reformation and Protestantism and applied to politics, provided the intellectual basis for a social contract theory. At its heart is the idea that legitimate government is the artificial product of the voluntary agreement of free moral agents, and that there is no »natural« political authority. So its basic preoccupations are questions of legitimacy of the state and of consent of the people to the form of government. The golden age of social contract theory was the period 1650-1800, beginning with Hobbes's Leviathan and ending with Kant's Metaphysical Elements of Justice1 and it also includes writers such as Locke, Rousseau and Spinoza. So let us first take a look at Hobbes's classical theory of social contract which was the basis for all the following social contract theories. Hobbes's purpose was to give the theory of stable and human commonwealth and the theory of sovereign power within it as its precondition. Commonwealth or civil society is an »artificial« product, established by each of its members with his consent as an act of will, what distinguishes it from »state of nature«. Thus Hobbes says: 1. See David Miller et al., eds., The Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought, Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1987, article Social Contract by Patrick Riley. 98 Gorazd Korošec »The right of all sovereigns is derived originally from consent of every one of those that are to be governed. J Hobbes's theory of social contract, and the same can be claimed for all contractarianism, is a doctrine of »will and artifice«, as maintains Michael Oakeshott. We shall to some extent follow Hobbes's argument with his brilliant and famous Introduction to the 1946 edition of Leviathan. Oakeshott points out one fundamental conclusion which underlies all Hobbes's political theory and contains what was in Hobbes's view the fundamental »law of nature«: »Where there is a number of men, felicity is impossible of attainment unless each man acts so as not to do to another what he would not have done to himself.«? The conditional and negative form of the conclusion are both essential, claims Oakeshott, because conclusions of reasoning are necessarily conditional and because Hobbes's conception of the character of the individual is such that one man can promote the felicity of another only negatively by forbearance, not by activity. Hobbes himself claims that this conclusion belongs to the »unwritten laws«, and explains: »Unwritten laws are all of them laws of nature. And first, if it be a law that obliges all the subjects without exception, and is not written, nor otherwise published in such places as they may take notice thereof, it is a law of nature. For whatsoever men are to take knowledge of for law, not upon other men's words, but every one from his own reason, must be such as is agreeable to the reason of all men; which no law can be, but the law of nature. The laws of nature therefore need not any publishing, nor proclamation; as being contained in this one sentence, approved by all the world, Do not that to another, which thou thinkest unreasonable to be done by another to thyself.«4 It is not mere coincidence at all, although it may appear as such for someone, that this unwritten law of nature is stated in almost Kantian words. All tradition of social contract theory namely speaks about universal and natural laws in this manner. And the other name for such natural laws, as Hobbes says, is moral laws. Hobbes's other conclusions regarding establishment of a commonwealth, logically follows from this first one: »1) Where there is a number of men, felicity is impossible unless each man is willing, in agreement with each other man, to surrender his natural right to 2 . Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, (1651) ed. Michael Oakeshott, Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1946, III, ch. 42. 3 . Michael Oakeshott, Introduction to Hobbes's Leviathan, in: Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, p. xxxvi. Cf. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, I, ch. 14, p. 85; I, ch. 15, 103; II, ch. 26, 177; III, ch. 30, 226. 4 . Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan. II, ch. 26, p. 177. Hobbes and the theory of social contract... 99 pursue his own felicity as if he were alone in the world, the surrender being equal to all men.«' This is the only way of achieving the principal goal of a commonwealth or civil society, namely security of each of its members and maintaining peace, because the exercise of the natural Right, that is unlimited use of power of each individual in pursuing his good, leads in war of all against all, and therefore frustrates those desirable ends. So the exercise of this natural Right must be surrendered equally from all, with a primal agreement and covenant performed by all: »2) Where there is a number of men, felicity is impossible unless each man performs his promises under the agreement he makes with each other man.«.6 Commonwealth members are bound by their covenant, the covenant of surrendering the unlimited natural Right, and therefore this Right cannot be held intact. But this, of course, does not mean, that they had surrendered all means of pursuing felicity. To surrender an absolute right to do something on all occasions does not mean to give up the right of doing it on any occasion. Men are free to do all things that do not frustrate the ultimate end of establishing the commonwealth or - for to maintain that end (that is, peace and security of each member) is the purpose of laws of the commonwealth - that are not forbidden by laws. When law is silent, an individual is sovereign. Therefore: »3) Where there is a number of men, felicity is impossible unless it is understood that, notwithstanding any agreement entered into, no man shall be held to ha ve promised to act in such a way as to preclude his further pursuit of felicity. «* This is, in a few short statements, a starting point of the Hobbes's doctrine. But it is also its core, for these conditions are foundations on which the whole theoretical building rests. And every commonwealth, in Hobbes's view, stays with these conditions and collapses, if they are not fulfilled. The right and only duty of a sovereign, be it a man, or an assembly of men, or, as in the case of England, the King in Parliament, is to make laws. As Oakeshott says, the sovereign has the general duty of being successful,8 so he cannot make any laws, but good laws. And such are those that are not frustrating the principal end of commonwealth. Because by making a covenant all the people have established a commonwealth, they have authorized the laws of the sovereign by their consent. »It is in the laws of a commonwealth, as in the laws of gaming, whatsoever the gamesters all agree on, is injustice to 5 . Michael Oakeshott, Introduction, p. xxxvii. Cf. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, I, ch. 14, p. 85. 6 . Ibid. Cf. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, I, ch. 15, pp. 93-6. 7 . Ibid. Cf. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, I, ch. 14, pp. 86-7; II, ch. 21, p. 142. 8 . Ibid, p. xl. 100 Gorazd Korošec none of them,«* says Hobbes. So it cannot be said for any law, made by the authority of a sovereign, that is unjust. But law must also be a good one, that is, needful, made for the good of the people, and necessary, for only such laws have the true aim of a law. It should set hedges and then not stop travellers, but keep them on their way. The good of the sovereign and good of people are inseparable, so the sovereign that has weak subjects, or wants power to rule them at his will, is himself weak. Nor is there the only danger of making unnecessary laws in their superfluity, but it also lies in the fact that in making wrong laws, the sovereign makes laws that are insufficient to defend the people, which is the principal task he must perform. Hobbes was often accused and condemned as an absolutist or even a totalitarian, but that is not true at all. Indeed he maintains that sovereign power in all commonwealths ought to be absolute,10 but this claim is easily understood, if we know first that the alternative of such power is perpetual war of every man against every other, and second that in the case where every command or, what is the same, law of the sovereign will can be obeyed or disobeyed by choice, or in the case where we have a number of unauthorised powers in society that can prevent realisation of, or even annulate any law, the result would be the same as in the former case; civil society could no longer exist. But Hobbes maintains that liberty of the subjects is consistent with the unlimited power of the sovereign,11 if this power corresponds to the demands we describe above, of course. How is this possible? Although we can distinguish civil law and the law of nature as written and unwritten law, Hobbes maintains that they contain each other and are of equal extent.12 Laws of nature or moral laws, namely equity, justice and gratitude, are, in the condition of nature, only qualities that dispose man to obedience and peace. They become laws only when the commonwealth is established and when they become civil laws or commands of the commonwealth. Only then are they binding and have the power to punish the breach of such a law. » The la w of nature therefore is a part of the civil la w in all common wealths of the world. Reciprocally also, the civil law is the part of the dictates of nature. For justice, that is to say, performance of covenant, and giving to every man his own, is a dictate of the law of nature. But every subject in a commonwealth, hath covenanted to obey the civil law; either one with another, as when they assemble to make a common representative, or with the representative itself one by one, when subdued by the sword they promised 9 . Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, II, eh. 30, p. 227. As we can see, Wittgenstein was not so innovative in this respect. 10. Ibid.. II, ch. 20, p. 136. I t . Ibid., II, ch. 21, p. 139. 12 . Ibid., II, ch. 26, p. 174. Hobbes and the theory of social contract... 101 obedience, that they may receive life; and therefore obedience to the civil law is part also of the la w of nature. «" The only reason why law was brought into the world is to limit the absolute and unrestricted natural liberty of men. But as we see, Hobbes's words are not mere constatation. They consist in the demand that the relation between civil laws and laws of nature must be such as described. We can also see why, as Hobbes says, all laws need interpretation,14 including the laws of nature, the only valid interpretation being that of the sovereign power. For laws must speak equally to all subjects, not being subjected to arbitrary interpretations of different authorities or even each and every individual, as is the case, for example, with the mere laws of nature. One can see in this Hobbes's principal egalitarianism or, on the other hand, authoritarianism, but we shall rather say that this aligns him among the first theorists of the Rule of law, and among the strongest. In spite of the fact that laws of nature too need interpretation of the sovereign power, civil laws are limited by the laws of nature in the sense that only such law can be made a civil law, which is not contrary to the laws of nature. So Hobbes maintains that subjects are bound to obey all laws, which are not contrary to moral law, that is to say, to the law of nature. .» Which also is evident to any man's reason: for whatsoever is not against the law of nature, may be made law in the name of them that have the sovereign power, «r15 Moral law, or the law of nature, is therefore the limitation of civil law or civil legislation, a fact that has not been pointed out so often about Hobbes's theory. Nor is this all: even the sovereign must act in accordance with the laws he has made. In another case we cannot talk of the Rule of law. So a man has, even if he has a controversy with the sovereign, a liberty to sue for his right in a court of justice.16 We are thus approaching to the liberty of subjects. »Liberty, or freedom,« as Hobbes defines it, and this is a classical definition, »signifieth, properly, the absence of opposition; by opposition I mean external impediments of motion.«" And now follows the passage that Isaiah Berlin would later take as an example of a »negative« definition of liberty: »A FREEMAN, is he, that in those things, which by his strength and wit he is able to do, is not hindered to do what he has a will to. The greatest liberty of subjects depends on the silence of the law, although even obedience to the law leaves to a subject the freedom to perform an act 13. Ibid. 14. Ibid., p. 180. 15 . Ibid., p. 188. 16. Ibid., II, ch. 21, p. 143-4. 17 . Ibid., p. 136. 18 . Ibid, p. 137. 102 Gorazd Korošec which the law commands, in a way he holds most appropriate. But the true liberty of a subject according to Hobbes, is not one of these, but the liberty to disobey. Hobbes therefore asks: »What are the things, which though commanded by the sovereign, he [the subject] may nevertheless, without injustice, refuse to do.«?9 We must know, »what rights we pass away, when we make a commonwealth«, because »there being no obligation on any man, which ariseth not from some act of his own«}0 So liberty of subjects in a commonwealth, says Hobbes, consists in liberty from the covenants they made. But even the act of man's submission to the authority of the commonwealth, that is, the sovereign, which is at the same time the act of establishing the commonwealth and the institution of sovereignty, consists in both man's obligation and liberty. This act was, of course, performed with one particular end, namely security of a man and his life in peace and therefore limitations of his liberty as well as the extent of his obligations, are to be justified only from this particular end. So »it is manifest, that every subject has liberty in all those things, the right whereof cannot by covenant be transferredV Thus subjects have liberty or the right to protect their lives, bodies and persons and not to hurt or injure themselves in any way or abstain from any thing, without which they cannot live. So if interrogated, man does not need to accuse himself or testify against himself. Even »if the sovereign command a man, though justly condemned, to kill, wound, or maim himself... yet hath that man the liberty to disobey. This liberty to disobey is entirely in accordance with subject's consent, neccesary for the existence of commonwealth. As Hobbes states it: »Again, the consent of a subject to sovereign power, is contained in these words, I authorise, or take upon me, all his actions; in which there is no restriction at all, of his own former natural liberty...