Beauty as a four-fold paradox Alenka Zupančič In this study we will attend to the problem of the beautiful as it is posed in Kant's philosophy, where it is closely associated with the problem of the form. First of all, however, it is appropriate to make a problem out of the beautiful, that is to say, to point out the »problematical« status of the beautiful. The paradox of the beautiful arises above all from the fact that »scientific analysis« is of no use on this territory. Beauty does not stand the definition as long as the latter means positive determination of what makes something beautiful. - If such a definition of the beautiful were available, we would have missed what we call the »specifics of art«: by following certain rules or instructions anyone could produce beauty. The whole prestigious status, charm and spell of beauty is due to its quality of something that cannot be »captured«, to the fact that it cannot be reduced to the »actual« description of a certain object. Nevertheless, beauty is something we discuss extensively, make judgments about it, and try to articulate theoretically one way or another. We are concerned here precisely with the possibility of a theoretical articulation of the beautiful - bearing in mind that beauty eludes the fundamental apparatus of theory, i.e. the concept. One of the most productive attempts to pursue such a theoretical articulation is Kant's analysis of the beautiful, in which the very impossibility of the classic definition of the beautiful is taken as a positive starting point of the theory. As we are about to see, Kant tries to approach the beautiful in four steps, with four paradoxical definitions, the essential part of which is »the signifier of the lack«, the word without. (Beauty is »a liking without interest«, »universality without concept«, »purposiveness without purpose«, and »necessity without concept«.) The essential twist that Kant's analysis achieves is his conception of the lack, which is not tied only to our knowledge of the beautiful, but turns out to be in some intimate and irreducible relation to beauty itself. This is not simply the question of »some« lack. If we look a bit closer at the definitions quoted above, we will soon discover that with formulations as »X without Y« Kant always deprives the first concept (X) exactly of that (Y) which is regarded as its essential characterization. - Is it not the essence of every liking that it is bound with interest, is it not the essence of universality that it is based upon concept, is it 128 Alenka Zupančič not the essence of purposiveness that it has a purpose...? On the grounds of these paradoxical »descriptions« we could formulate Kant's »project« in the following way: we can achieve the qualities of the beautiful only by way of following the effect of beauty itself on these very qualities - what happens to a liking when it is tied to the beautiful, what happens to universality when it is tied to beauty...? This also represents the mode of our reading of Kant's theory. * Although the beautiful as a domain of the aesthetic is on the one hand defined as the third link, the link between theory and practice, it could, on another perspective, be read as the fourth moment: if the first three are sensibility, understanding and reason. Kant's theory of the aesthetic is based upon the concept of sense, but nevertheless it cannot be reduced to it. Aesthetics in the third Critique is not the theory of sensibility. When Kant introduced the concept of »transcendental aesthetics« in the first Critique he pointed out the double use of the word aesthetics. The difference between aesthetics as a theory of sensibility (which is the original meaning of the Greek aisthesis and which is at stake in Critique of Pure Reason) and aesthetics as a theory of the beautiful or a theory of judgements of taste is in the following: for sensibility as such it is possible to find a priori principles (space and time as a priori forms of sensibility) but this is altogether impossible for »sensibility« appearing in the phenomenon of the beautiful (a priori conditions of the beautiful cannot be defined). This is the main problem of the third Critique-, what do we base the discourse of the beautiful on if there is no defined (a priori) concept, law or purpose to rely on. - If, therefore, we can neither rely on theory nor practice, how do we then define the phenomenon of the beautiful? In the following pages we will follow Kant's analysis from § 1 to § 22, in which Kant tries to approach the definition of the beautiful in four steps, each representing a peculiar paradox. »Pure pleasure